Monographs
2024. Die Entstehung des Marburger Linkskantianismus. Anfänge und Entwicklungen 1865-1919, Königshausen und Neumann. Preprint Published Review (IFB) by Till Kinzel
AbstractIn dieser philosophiehistorischen Arbeit verteidige ich die These, dass sich am Ende des 19. Jahrhunderts im Marburger Neukantianismus eine dem Kapitalismus gegenüber kritisch eingestellte philosophische Strömung entwickelte, die ich ‚Linkskantianismus‘ nenne. In Anlehnung und Abgrenzung an den Linkshegelianismus zeichne ich historisch und systematisch die argumentativen Grundlinien bei Friedrich Albert Lange, Hermann Cohen und am Rande auch von Paul Natorp und Rudolf Stammler nach, um die Anfänge und einzelne Entwicklungen ein Stück weit nachzuverfolgen.
show less2023. Left-Kantianism in the Marburg School, De Gruyter. Preprint Published (open access) Review (Journal of Transcendental Philosophy) by Sabato Dezilli (open access)
AbstractThis book aims to show that, next to left-Hegelian Marxism, the long nineteenth century saw a current consisting of scholars who criticized capitalism on Kantian grounds. I subsume these theories under the operative umbrella term “Left-Kantianism.” This book focuses on a small part of this current: the Marburg School. Marburg Left-Kantianism is characterized by (i) a teleological perspective on rationality; (ii) their advocacy of socialism as a historical political movement; and (iii) a Kant-inspired methodology for formulating normative demands, grounded in the potential to foster societal progress. This book introduces their political philosophies with the aim of emphasizing the distinctness of their respective approaches with the hope of attracting and enhancing scholarly interest in this forgotten era.
show lessEdited Volumes
2025. Kant’s Early Followers in Political Philosophy, edited with Reidar Maliks, Routledge (forthcoming).
AbstractImmanuel Kant influenced a large and productive group of political philosophers in the 1790s. This volume argues that they brought out more fully the egalitarian principles of Kantian republicanism.m“The Kantian school” featured young philosophers including Saul Ascher, Johann Adam Bergk, Johann Benjamin Erhard, Johann Ludwig Ewald, the early Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Friedrich Schlegel, and Johann Heinrich Tieftrunk. They combined their commitment to Kant with a dedication to freedom, equality, popular sovereignty, and a people’s right to revolution. Furthermore, they sought to bring their notion of Kantian republicanism to bear on the political agenda in 1790s Germany. The chapters in this volume analyze their work in relation to Kant and their wider philosophical and political context. They advance three main theses. First, the Kantians defended popular sovereignty and several of them supported the extension of the right to vote to workers and women. Second, several of them developed a political perfectionism, the view that equal political rights are justified for their effects on cultivating moral character. Third, they developed sophisticated theories of state legitimacy and collective action, defending a people’s right to change their constitution, either through reform or through revolution.
Kant’s Early Followers in Political Philosophy offers a systematic view into a neglected group of thinkers at a foundational moment for modern political thought. It will be of interest to scholars and graduate students working on Kant, eighteenth-century philosophy, political philosophy, and the history of early modern German political thought.
Special Issues
2026. Left-Kantianism, edited by Elisabeth Widmer and Howard Williams, Kantian Review (forthcoming).
AbstractThis special issue explores various ‘left-Kantian’ traditions in which Kant is seen as a source of left-wing political ideas. It covers Kant’s contemporaries, comparisons with Marx, neo-Kantian left-wing philosophers, and critical theorists.
show less2026. Canonical Pluralism, edited by Bettina Bussmann and Elisabeth Widmer, Educational Theory and Philosphy (forthcoming).
AbstractIn contrast to academic philosophy, teaching philosophy consists largely of reading philosophers from the past. This approach presupposes selecting works and authors that culminate in a ‘canon’: a set of works or authors from a specific period deemed outstanding by individuals at a later period. The formation of a canon is inherently subject to tension: While the criteria for canonical relevance reflect the outcome of a collective deliberation process, guided by philosophical experts and educators, these criteria are prone to perpetuating the social biases of a dominant tradition, social group, or class. This tension is particularly pertinent in the educational context. On one hand, philosophy educators face the task of conveying thought traditions that preserve an intellectual history. On the other hand, educators ought to minimize the risk of adopting methods that perpetuate problematic social biases. To balance these aims, this special issue explores pluralistic approaches to canonical relevance. Canonical pluralism, as we understand it, suggests that in order to minimize social biases, philosophy education requires pluralistic standards of ‘relevance,’ reflected and integrated into the content of canons and teaching methods.
show less2026. The Noumenal Republic, edited by Elisabeth Widmer, Howard Williams and Lea Ypi, Kantian Review (forthcoming).
AbstractIn this issue, Rainer Forst responds to critical investigations of The Noumenal Republic by Sasha Mudd, Lois McNay, Howard Williams, Andrea Sangiovanni, Chris Meckstroth, and Elisabeth Widmer.
show lessJournal Articles (peer reviewed)
2025. “Max Adler’s Neo-Kantian Reinvention of Marx’s Notion of History,” Kantian Review (forthcoming). Preprint
AbstractAt the turn of the twentieth century, few philosophical ideas in Marx’s work gained as much attention as his account of history. Orthodox Marxists made it their programme to closely follow Marx’s development thesis, which posits that the productive forces determine the course of history. The Austromarxist Max Adler (1873-1937), influenced by neo-Kantianism, took more liberties in interpreting-or, perhaps more accurately, ‘reinventing’the law of history in practical terms. This article reconstructs Adler’s neo-Kantian ‘reinvention’ of Marx’s account of history. According to Adler, the notion of ‘necessity’ that underpins critical judgements is not grounded in the regularity of history but rather in the moral judgements we make about how history should develop. More specifically, I defend two claims. First, by interpreting human progress as a possibility that presents itself as a necessity from the standpoint of practical rationality, I show that Adler laid the foundation for a critique of the Marxist development thesis that only later gained traction. Second, while Marxists may fear that Kantian formalism cannot address misguided ideological beliefs, I argue that Adler’s neo-Kantian formalism is robustly anti-ideological, emphasising the ideology-emancipating transformation we undergo when we recognise exploitative structures.
show lessKant’s political philosophy has experienced a recent revival, largely due to influential interpretations that frame his concept of right as a republican account of “nondomination.” One of the major challenges in reconstructing Kant’s concept of law within neo-republican terms is his notion of citizenship. While neo-republicans have made substantial efforts to distance themselves from the traditional view that restricted voting rights to mainstream white men, Kant’s distinction between “active” and “passive” citizens still echoes this conventional line of thought. Without dismissing the prevalence of the sexist and classist prejudices inherent in Kant’s dichotomy, this paper argues that Kant introduces this distinction with the republican aim of securing a state governed by non-arbitrary laws. I contend that this aim explains Kant’s concern with the civic character of citizens and their ability to contest structures of domination-a line of argument that aligns him more closely with contemporary neo-republicanism.
show less2025. “Johann Benjamin Erhard on Economic Injustice,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy (forthcoming). Preprint
AbstractUnlike Johann Benjamin Erhard’s views on art, right, revolution, and structural misrecognition, his discussion of economic injustice, here understood as the lawful economic oppression of one’s end-setting human nature, has garnered little attention. To begin filling this gap, I focus on central passages from his 1795 book On the Right of the People to a Revolution wherein Erhard discusses two cases of economic injustice. By reconstructing these claims within his Kantian perfectionist framework, I pursue two goals. First, I seek to demonstrate that his fundamental ‘duty to oneself’ lays out a comprehensive framework for duties grounding moral obligations to remedy economic practices. My second aim is to utilize this framework to explain how he defends a natural law position that views the legal system as both a remedy for and an ideological tool of economic oppression. I argue that this two-fold perspective is a strength of Erhard’s theory as it allows for the detection of oppressive economic structures without letting go of a principle of external freedom from where coercive juridical laws can be derived.
show lessHermann Cohen, the founding father of Marburg neo-Kantianism, is known for criticizing capitalism from a Kantian ethical perspective. Thus far, the role of the notion of humanity has been viewed as grounding the-what I shall call-‘purposive-labour reading’. This interpretation suggests that Cohen aimed at a reorganization of work so that our humanity, which requires us to be treated as ends, remains intact. With the aim to better understand his usage of humanity, I contextualize the discussion of socialism and capitalism within Cohens’ overall framework and situate his ideas in the context of his contemporary interlocutors. Revisiting Cohen’s remarks on socialism and capitalism against the backdrop of his neo-Kantian account of ethical cognition reveals that his discussion of labour serves as an exemplar, showcasing how ethical rationality manifests in the liberal socialists’ demands. I argue that his primary aim was not to prepare the ground for a prescriptive labour theory — though this is likely to follow — but to argue for an alternative framework to historical materialism, allowing us to perceive and interpret social practices in an ethical light.
show less2024. “Objectivity and Truth in Ernst Cassirer’s Ethics,” Continental Philosophy Review (forthcoming). Preprint
AbstractCassirer’s view on ethical objectivity is puzzling. In his scarce comments on Kantian ethics, the “pure will” is defined as a “function of consciousness,” which he takes to be a necessary condition of the possibility of objective ethical normativity embedded in empirical reality. In the current literature, we find two distinct interpretations of Cassirer’s account of ethical objectivity. The ‘meta-philosophical’ interpretation takes objectivity as a telos that humanity gradually approaches, thereby emphasizing the historically relative truth standards to which the teleologically-evolving symbolic forms respond. The ‘Kantian’ interpretation takes objectivity as a concept inherent to the conduct of the moral law, highlighting the evaluative and prescriptive aspects of Cassirer’s philosophical method. By interpreting Cassirer’s ethics in light of Hermann Cohen’s mature ethical theory, I argue that ethical deliberation in Cassirer entails a notion of universality that is a priori and reliant on a substantiated concept that is subject to change. The proposed ‘contingent conception of universality’ thesis accounts for both: the evaluative and teleological features of Cassirer’s ethical theory, grounding an a priori account of ethical objectivity conceptualized relative to contingent truth standards that gradually improve.
show less2023. “‘Left-Kantianism’ and the ‘Scientific Dispute’ between Rudolf Stammler and Hermann Cohen.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie. Preprint Published (open access)
AbstractThis paper argues that the ‘scientific dispute’ between Hermann Cohen and Rudolf Stammler is symptomatic of a philosophical movement of left-wing Kant interpretations at the turn of the twentieth century. By outlining influential predecessors that shaped Cohen’s and Stammler’s thinking, I show that their Kantian justifications of socialism differ regarding their conception of law, history, and the political implications that follow from their practical philosophies. Against scholars who suggest that the Marburg School’s view on socialism was a coherent school of thought, I introduce the concept of ‘left-Kantianism’ as an open term that includes a wide variety of novel socialist approaches to Kant at the time.
show less2022. “A Contextualist Approach to Teaching Antisemitism in Philosophy Class.” Journal of Didactics of Philosophy (co-authored with Henriikka Hannula). Published (open access)
AbstractThis paper argues for a ‘contextualist’ approach to teaching antisemitism in philosophy class. The traditional ‘systematic’ approach emphasizes recognizing and dismantling antisemitic aspects in canonical philosophical texts. The introduced contextualist approach broadens the perspective, treating philosophy as a continuous debate embedded in cultural realities. It focuses on historical controversies rather than isolated arguments, includes the voice and the perspectives of the oppressed, and so has the potential to broaden traditional philosophical canons. In the second half of the paper, we provide a case study of the contextualist approach, applying it to the ‘Berlin antisemitism controversy’ of 1879/80. We argue that the contextualist approach is particularly valuable when dealing with antisemitism as it teaches students to analyze arguments within the socio-political landscape and to identify antisemitic elements. The students thereby acquire the skills to discern antisemitic argumentation in other contexts as well. We suggest that this approach could be used to teach other debates in the history of philosophy, especially those tackling race, sex, and gender issues.
show less2022. “Psychophysiological Transcendentalism in Friedrich Albert Lange’s Social and Political Philosophy.” Journal of Transcendental Philosophy. Published (open access)
AbstractIn recent literature, it has been suggested that Lange’s social and political philosophy is separate from his neo-Kantian program. Prima facie, this interpretation makes sense given that Lange argues for an account of social norms that builds on Darwin and Smith rather than on Kant. Still, this paper argues that elements of psychophysiological transcendentalism can be found in Lange’s social and political philosophy. A detailed examination of the second edition of the History of Materialism, Schiller’s Poems, and the second edition of The Worker’s Question reveals that Lange sought to develop a systematic foundation of psychophysiological transcendentalism that is presupposed in his social and political philosophy. This allows for a more detailed understanding of Lange’s practical philosophy and assures him a position in the tradition of neo-Kantian socialism.
show less2021. “Elements of Völkerpsychologie in Hermann Cohen’s Mature Ethical Idealism.” Idealistic Studies. Preprint Published
AbstractThis paper challenges the hitherto common distinction between Hermann Cohen’s early phase of Völkerpsychologie and his later phase as a critical idealist. Recently, it has been claimed that Cohen’s turn was not a rapid conversion but a development that was already inherent to his early view. This paper argues that even in Cohen’s mature critical idealism, a thin basis of Völkerpsychologie continues to exist. Cohen’s critical programme is presented as having a twofold aim: On the one hand, it strives to give an account of pure, formal, and logical laws that regulate critical thinking; on the other hand, it offers a reading of Kant’s dualism between matter and form that allows critical thinking to be seen as inevitably embedded in causal laws of psychology, history, and physiology. Concerning the latter, the paper argues that Cohen remained in the tradition of Völkerpsychologie in his mature ethical thought.
show lessBook Chapters
2025. “Johann Benjamin Erhard’s Critical Account of State Legitimacy,” In Kant’s Early Followers in Political Philosophy, edited by Elisabeth Widmer and Reidar Maliks, Routledge (forthcoming). Preprint
AbstractThere are many ways to conceptualize state legitimacy, one approach being through the lens of human rights. While thinking of state legitimacy in terms of human rights gained prominence after the Second World War, Johann Benjamin Erhard had already compiled a list of human rights in his 1795 moral justification of revolution, positing that a state’s legitimacy in exercising coercion hinges on its ability to secure these rights. In this chapter, I shall argue that Erhard’s human rights account is novel in two significant respects. First, from a historical viewpoint, I argue that by placing humanity at the forefront of his philosophy, Erhard—alongside other revolutionary Kantians—presented a novel approach to state legitimacy that was notably unconventional before the 1790s. Second, from a systematic point of view, I shall show that Erhard’s innovative use of the Kantian distinction between humanity-grounding duties “in themselves” and “in relation to an end” paves the way for a “critical” usage of human rights to identify existing oppressive structures. Highlighting this aspect will support a recently made suggestion to consider him a “proto-critical theorist.”
show less2024. “Cassirer’s Kantian Ethical Hermeneutics: A Contextualist Approach to the History of Political Ideas,” In Kant and Cassirer: Legacy — Interpretation — Frontiers, edited by Luigi Filieri and Konstantin Pollok, Cassirer Forschungen (forthcoming). PDF upon request
AbstractQuentin Skinner criticizes Cassirer for an inaccurate depiction of the history of philosophy, as, on his account, Kant is portrayed as the pinnacle of the history of philosophy. Grounded in the epistemological and normative premise that philosophical ideas are properly understood only when studied within the context of their initial articulation, Skinner argues for the necessity to ‘contextualize’ philosophical ideas. In this article, I argue that, despite the weaknesses Skinner points out in Cassirer’s historiography, Cassirer nonetheless provides us with a Kantian-ethical framework of contextualism that is better equipped to address two hermeneutical problems arising in Skinner’s account. By highlighting the similarities and differences to Kant, I argue that Cassirer’s hermeneutics is developed based on an account of progress grounded in what I call the ‘deontological efficacy’ thesis, a will-based account of progress that abstracts the contingent aspects of history and evaluates the intended aim of a theory in its effort to overcome the oppressive structures of its time.
show less2024. “Neo-Kantian Genealogy: The Critique of Culture in the Marburg School,” In Cambridge Handbook of Continental Philosophy, edited by Karen Ng and Sacha Golob, Cambridge University Press (forthcoming). Preprint
AbstractThe Marburg neo-Kantian school is widely acknowledged as a precursor to analytic philosophy. Consisting of philosophers such as Friedrich Albert Lange (1828-1875), Hermann Cohen (1842-1918), Paul Natorp (1854-1924), Rudolf Stammler (1856-1938), and Ernst Cassirer (1874-1945), their anti-metaphysical and purely “critical” interpretation of the Kantian principles provided important ideas for Rudolf Carnap (Damböck 2017). Their approaches also laid the groundwork for the so-called “continental-analytical divide”—a division that traces back to a debate that emerged between Ernst Cassirer, advocating for the analytical side, and Martin Heidegger, representing the continental side (Truwant 2022, Friedman 2000). Recently, however, scholars have paid increasing attention to their historicization of rationality (Edgar 2022, Kinzel 2021, Clarke 2021, Biagioli 2021, Pecere 2021, Renz 2021). This particular aspect piqued the curiosity of genealogical thinkers within the continental tradition, who otherwise tend to approach idealist and rationalist interpretations in the Kantian tradition with skepticism. The aim of this chapter is to introduce and delineate the fundamental characteristics of the Marburg school’s evolutionary perspectives on rationality. By doing so, it seeks to clarify how genealogists, despite their reservations towards Kantian rational idealism, were intrigued by the neo-Kantian tradition.
show less2022. “Friedrich Albert Langes materialistisch-poetische Kant-Interpretation und die Konsequenzen in der Ethik.” In Kant um 1900, edited by Hauke Heidenreich and Friedrich Stengel, De Gruyter. Preprint Published
Review
2022. “Luigi Filieri, Anne Pollok, (eds). 2021. The Method of Culture. Ernst Cassirer’s Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Pisa: Edizioni ETS, pp.295, ISBN 8846761006, 9788846761002.” Journal of Transcendental Philosophy. Published (open access)